Is it possible to colour all positive real numbers by 10 colours so that every two numbers with decimal representations differing in one place only are of different colours? (We suppose that there is no place in a decimal representations such that all digits starting from that place are 9's.) Proposed by A. Golovanov
Problem
Source: Tuymaada 2001, day 2, problem 4.
Tags: function, combinatorics proposed, combinatorics
08.05.2007 23:38
Nice problem! I have a solution that uses my beloved Axiom of Choice Let us define the equivalence relation between positive real numbers: "$a \equiv b$ if $a-b$ has only finitely non-zero digits". It is reflexive (a-a = 0 that doesn't have non-zero digits), symmetric (a-b = -(b-a) and they have the same digits) and transitive ( $(a-b)+(b-c) = (a-c)$ and the sum of two numbers of the form $\frac{n}{10^{k}}$ is of this form). So, this equivalence relations partitions the set of positive reals in a family of disjoint sets (classes of equivalence). Let $f(a)$ be the equivalence class containing a. Let $g$ be a choice function of the equivalence classes (and here we use AC). Now we finally define $c: \mathbb{R}^{+}\rightarrow \mathbb{Z}_{10}$ such that c(r) is the sum of the decimal digits (mod 10) of $a-g(f(a))$. In fact, $a \equiv g(f(a))$, so their difference has just a finite number of nonzero digits, and we can calculate this sum. If two numbers a,b differ only in one place of their decimal rappresentation, $c(a)-c(b)$ is the sum of the decimal digits of their difference, that by hypotesis has one and only one nonzero digit $\Rightarrow c(a) \neq c(b)$. Is it clear? Now I ask you either to prove this problem without the Axiom of Choice, or to prove (a weak form of) the Axiom of Choice using this problem